Overreacting to creationism in Ohio

So yet again creationism is flaring up, this time in a small Ohio town.  Right now it looks like a lot of he said-she said.   Did the teacher actually burn a cross on the student’s arm, or was it just an experiment gone wrong?  Did he refuse to remove a Bible from his desk? Is there anything wrong about having a Bible on your desk?  And most importantly, was he actually teaching creationism?

I tend to have mixed feelings about this perpetual conflict.   I don’t think creationism should be in science classrooms…but I also think that people often overreact to the controversy.  This teacher appears to have an exemplary record over 20-odd years–including a couple teaching awards.  His transgressions are much milder than passing out from drinking too much in the middle of class, or some other horror stories we hear about.   Surely we can solve this situation without suing someone.  I suspect that it’s pretty hard to get top-quality science teachers in central Ohio.  Is it really necessary to react so harshly for someone for disagrees with what is no more than 3 weeks of a typical high school biology class?  Maybe it would be easier to find a substitute for those weeks.

Granted there are probably logistical, legal and regulatory impediments to this type of solution.  But even if they could be overcome, I bet most most people would oppose this solution.  There’s something about this issue that gets everyone’s blood to boil.   We’re not even interested in working out what are, in my view, pretty minor disagreements.  Everyone has some primal desire to crucify the other side.

Indefinite articles need not apply

Continuing yet again with the science and teamwork idea, it’s interesting to observe that scientists rarely use the indefinite article a when talking about science.  Science is the foundation, the basis, and the reason for any action.  It is never simply a reason.  Why not seek out other justifications for climate change policy?  Why does it have to be mainly about science?

Passing out of the triple-team

Let’s continue with the science-as-part-of-a-team meme and see how scientists neglect it to our detriment.  Consider anthropogenic global warming (AGW).  The skeptics who oppose any action to reduce greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions typically make this argument:

  1. These scientific facts show the Earth is not warming and/or humans are not the cause.
  2. Ergo, we should not waste any time trying to reduce GHGs.

This argument assumes that once we’ve proven a certain set of facts, nothing else matters.  Now in this particular case, the specific facts employed happen to be utterly and completely wrong.  Pointing out these factual errors is usually the standard response.  But in doing so climate scientists are playing on the skeptics’ turf.  They’re still assuming that we need science and nothing but science to make an argument for reducing GHGs. *

But why should action to reduce GHGs depend only on science and nothing but science?  Surely there are spiritual, ethical, economic and social reasons to drive less, use more efficient light bulbs, etc.  But that’s not how the debate will ever play out if we view science as the basis for decisions.

I hope we’re starting to see why neglecting the team mentality undermines effective policy-making.  Us scientists can be the basis or the foundation for decisions-making.  But then we shouldn’t be shocked when others distort or politicize it.  They’re doing exactly what we want them to…using science as the basis for decisions!

If instead science is simply part of a team and there are many reasons to reduce GHGs, then the skeptics’ argument loses its power.   But let’s be clear what this means.  It means that science is not necessarily privileged.  Science becomes simply a rather than the basis for decisions.   We may end up justifying climate policy on ethics and economics more than on atmospheric chemistry.   In some cases the science may be completely ignored.

This outcome shouldn’t worry us.   After all in this situation those opposing climate legislation will then have to contend with a helluva lot more than the latest IPCC report.  They’ll have to contend with religious leaders, economists, and philosophers along with scientists.  If this approach eventually helps us win the game, does it really matter if we don’t score as many points as we usually do?  Right now skeptics are triple-teaming the scientific community and we’re refusing to pass the ball! How dumb is that?

I’d really love to hear a scientist say: “You know what, who cares about the science? There are 100,000 reasons to reduce GHGs.  Science may not even be that important!”

In the end we can have our glory by being the basis for decisions or we can be effective in policy-making.  But we can’t always be both at the same time.

*Roger Pielke Jr, Dan Sarewitz and others have explored in great detail why this framing leads to ineffective policy-making.   I don’t want to repeat what they’ve said.  I’m instead trying to focus on how scientists’ worsen the situation by placing science on a pedestal and not thinking of themselves as part of a team.

(Some of) my goals for this blog…

By now I have written a handful of posts, including a brilliant, intoxicating treatise on death by terrorism.   (The fact that my argument contains not even the tiniest trace of originality does not, in my view, impugn its brilliance.)  I figure it’s a good time to sketch out some vague goals I have.  So here it goes.

I just started exploring the connection between science and team sports.  I’m going to really expand on this idea in greater detail.  In fits and starts, I will try to paint this picture:

  1. When scientists speak about science, we portray conflicting images.  On one hand, science is part of a team, does not dictate decision-making, and cannot by itself improve the human condition.  On the other, science is the foundation of any decision and is without a doubt the most important factor in any problem.
  2. Scientists really believe the latter image is correct, and most of our words reflect this belief.
  3. Scientists also want the public to agree with us.  i.e., we want everyone to also think that science is the most important thing.  So for the most part our public messaging paints this picture.
  4. Our belief in the primacy of science affects how we act in , e.g., political controversies and lobbying.
  5. When we act in political controversies, we face goals that conflict.  Specifically, our goal of placing science on a pedestal conflicts with our goal of, e.g., effective climate change policy.
  6. We almost always choose to emphasize the former, thereby somewhat undermining any other goal we may have.
  7. To accomplish our secondary goals, scientists should truly internalize the idea that we’re part of a team.  At times, this may entail demoting science. To run with the team sports analogy, everyone rides the bench at some point!

I should stress that excluding point 7, I am not necessarily advocating for a specific position.  It may or may not be a good thing for science to be placed on a pedestal.  But I believe that doing so inevitably and definitely conflicts with effective policy making.  Of course this begs the question of what I mean by “effective.”  I’ll have to define that at some point.  In short, a big goal of this blog will be to explore the idea that how scientists think about science affects how we act. And that these actions have consequences for much more than science.

Finally, I’ll say that I suspect suspect many (most?) scientists disagree with me.  They might say that we’re not really placing ourselves on a pedestal.  Or that doing so is the best way to address climate policy.  Or maybe that we really deserve to be on a pedestal!  But complete agreement would be quite boring, no?

Even more finally, the overwhelming likelihood is that nothing I write is original.  I have probably already plagiarized from 10 different scholars.  I apologize for any existing and future transgressions.

There is no science in team

In the dozens of science policy talks I’ve attended over the years (yes I know my life is interesting), I’ve noticed two very mixed messages that continually appear.  Somewhere in the introductory slides, the speaker inevitably mentions  Vannevar Bush’s seminal report “Science: The Endless Frontier.”  This sentence often comes up:
“Science can be effective in the national welfare only as a member of a team, whether the conditions be peace or war.”
If not this direct quote, I hear something like “science is only one input to decision-making.”  Or perhaps “science by itself does not dictate a specific policy.”

I’ll also hear quite often that “science is the foundation of decision-making.”  Sometimes linchpin or basis replaces foundation.  Both “good policy requires good science”  and “science underlies policy” are also standard.  The funny thing is that these two positions might appear in the same talk given by the same speaker.  They might even appear on two consecutive slides.

I’ve never heard anyone point out that these two positions are not entirely compatible.  What, exactly, does it mean for science to be “the foundation” of policy?  Does it mean science has to come first? Or that it’s the most important?  It’s not clear to me.  The upshot of all this is more than mere semantics, as important as that may be.   Viewing science as teamwork can lead to different actions than viewing it as foundational.

I can’t shake the feeling that us scientists simply pay lip-service to the former idea, but we really internalize the latter.  Thinking this way has, I believe, very real consequences for how we interact and communicate.  I’ll try expand more in the coming weeks.

Towards a semantics of science

My friend Tommer and I have been engaged in a year-long, cross country, international debate on the philosophy of science.   It all started in Christmas Eve 2008 during an epic frisbee golf game in Golden Gate Park in San Francisco.  It continued when I moved to the East Coast, during my vacation to Jamaica, and back again in San Francisco.  On that fateful day, in between the  trash-talk and excessive beer consumption, we started discussing the falsifiability of scientific theories and the scientific method.

I realize you’re very jealous you couldn’t take part in all this fun.  To help you get over the loss, let me engage you.  Here’s how I think the whole thing played out:
Me:  The scientific method (TSM) is useless donkey shit and doesn’t tell you anything useful for public policy.  Tommer, you’re an idiot for believing otherwise.
Tommer:  Praj, you’re a complete douche.  TSM has clearly helped us understand the world better.  Without it astrology would still govern our understanding of the universe and science would be no different than punditry.

Now of course there was a little more subtlety and detail over the 30-odd emails we exchanged.  But if you look past the personal insults (about 1 every 7.34 sentences), I think our VERY SHARP disagreements came down to nothing more than semantics.  I should probably admit that I was more guilty of the personal insults than Tommer was.  In my defense, insulting him made me very happy.  But I digress.

If I finally understand everything–there’s a good chance I don’t–we simply meant different things by the word “method.”  What should have been a fairly minor issue really colored our entire interaction.  I think the standard definition of TSM is too vague to constitute as a “method.”  The expression “hypothesize, test, verify, etc.” cannot tell us whether to use a thermometer or telescope in a given problem (Tommer’s example).  I believe that a “method” should be restrictive enough to identify the proper approach.  Tommer disagrees.

Now there’s probably some middle ground…I suspect that my definition of method is too strong while Tommer’s is too weak.  Nevertheless it’s interesting how much that single word affects how we both view the utility of TSM.

The upshot of all this is I think there should be more time spent on the semantics of science.  Let’s ignore for now the definition of science.  What do we mean by “method?”  What do we mean by “the” in TSM? Is there one specific method, or many? If there are many, whey do we use “the” instead of “a?”

Some quick googling reveals this book.  Looks like a bunch of philosophical gobbledygook, but I’ll have to investigate more.

I will post more about this soon.  But now I have to go see the Pat-Ravens game.  The Ravens just went up 21-0 and the first quarter isn’t even over.  I really hope the Pats lose!

All deaths are not equal

Right before New Year’s Eve, Andrew Sullivan’s blog saw some chatter about the tradeoffs between dying in a terrorist attack versus a car accident.  Apparently 113 Boeing 777’s must be exploded before terrorism can kill as many people as car accidents.  Yet people don’t scream for protection from their Buicks!  Bill Maher makes a similar argument in this entertaining video.

And why not?  A death is a death is a death….right? If our goal is overall safety, then surely the public should clamor for safer roads as much as they do for airports…right? Well, not quite.  As much as I agree that we spend too much on terrorism, both Sullivan and Bill Maher gloss over the important fact that deaths cannot always be treated equally.

Social science research has shown quite conclusively that these calculations inevitably involve a subjective value judgment on how to treat human life.  To quote Paul Slovic’s excellent paper:  “Simply counting fatalities treats the deaths of the old and young as equivalent; it also treats as equivalent deaths that come from immediately after mishaps  and deaths that follow painful and debilitating disease…”

Slovic continues to explain that distributional impacts (affecting black rather than white, poor rather than rich) and degree of control also affect risk perceptions.  People may be more forgiving if they knowingly engage in a risky activity as opposed to one where they are guaranteed safety.  We would, I hope, be very upset if a chemical plant discharge solely affects a community of poor, uneducated blacks even if only a couple dozen people died every year.   Calibrating our response to nothing more than total deaths elides these subtleties.

Along these lines, it doesn’t seem that unreasonable for people to demand strong government action on terrorism rather than automobile safety.  Perhaps they accept a certain risk of driving a car but don’t do so when flying a plane.  Perhaps they think getting blown up is somehow worse than a car crash.  Or perhaps they think we have done all we can to improve car safety but haven’t done nearly enough in other areas.  Again…accounting just for total deaths misses all this.

Maher et al. are of course free to say that we should treat car crashes and exploding planes equally.  They’re entitled to that belief.  But it represents their own subjective preference rather than a uniquely rational calculation.   Scientists’ acting otherwise is a main reason the public often sharply disagree with risk assessments.  Pretending our risk models are wholly rational also contributes to poor communication and mutual distrust.

None of this undermines the idea that we overemphasize the threat from terrorism.  I largely agree the sentiment.  But those arguments shouldn’t rest on a faulty analysis that simply sums total deaths in various activities.  While all lives should be treated equally, all deaths should not.

UPDATE: I meant to add this reference the first time.  Email me if you want a PDF copy.
Paul Slovic, The risk game, Journal of Hazardous Materials, 86 (2001), 17 – 24

I’m (sort of) back…

Hello world.  One of my New Years Resolutions (which I generally take very seriously) was to start blogging and writing more.  Creating this site was the first step, and replaces my dying personal blog at http://prajk.blogspot.com.  Here I’ll mostly post on science, policy and politics.  In the off chance that anyone reads my posts, comments will be appreciated.